edinburgh university press philosophy of international law mar 2007

272 297 0
edinburgh university press philosophy of international law mar 2007

Đang tải... (xem toàn văn)

Tài liệu hạn chế xem trước, để xem đầy đủ mời bạn chọn Tải xuống

Thông tin tài liệu

ANTHONY CARTY A fundamental challenge to the foundations of the discipline of international law. This book offers an internal critique of the discipline of international law whilst showing the necessary place for philosophy within this subject area. By reintroducing philosophy into the heart of the study of international law, Anthony Carty explains how traditionally philosophy has always been an integral part of the discipline. However, this has been driven out by legal positivism, which has, in turn, become a pure technique of law. He explores the extent of the disintegration and confusion in the discipline and offers various ways of renewing philosophical practice. A range of approaches are covered – post- structuralism, neo-Marxist geopolitics, social- democratic constitutional theory and existential phenomenology – encouraging the reader to think afresh about how far to bring order to, or find order in, contemporary international society. Key Features • Offers a broad survey of possible philosophical approaches to international law • Provides a fundamental critique of the basic techniques of the international lawyer • Includes case studies of colonial style interventions, the problem of American Empire and a vision of the shape of post- imperial, post-colonial world society Anthony Carty is Professor of Public Law at the University of Aberdeen. Jacket design: River Design, Edinburgh Jacket image: Kurt Hutton/Hulton Archive/ Getty Images Shawcross at the Hague Court in 1948: ‘[ . . . ] Parties to litigation are not entitled to use merely those documents which they think will assist their case and to suppress others which are inimical to it. [ . . . ] As it is, we retain great misgivings about the propriety of what is being done, which we can only justify on the principle “my country [ . . . ] right or wrong my country”.’ Hartley Shawcross to Prime Minister, 3 November 1948, The Corfu Channel Case Edinburgh University Press 22 George Square Edinburgh EH8 9LF www.eup.ed.ac.uk ISBN 978 0 7486 2255 9 Edinburgh barcode Philosophy of International Law Philosophy of International Law ANTHONY CARTY ANTHONY CARTY Philosophy of International Law PHILOSOPHY OF INTERNATIONAL LAW M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page i Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Jobs To the Memory of my Parents M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page ii Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Job Philosophy of International Law Anthony Carty Edinburgh University Press M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page iii Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Jo © Anthony Carty, 2007 Edinburgh University Press Ltd 22 George Square, Edinburgh Typeset in Adobe Sabon by Servis Filmsetting Ltd, Manchester, and printed and bound in Great Britain by Biddles Ltd, King’s Lynn, Norfolk A CIP record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN 978 0 7486 2255 9 (hardback) The right of Anthony Carty to be identified as the author of this work has been asserted in accordance with the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988. M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page iv Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Job CONTENTS Preface and Acknowledgments vi 1What Place for Doctrine in a Time of Fragmentation? 1 2 Continuing Uncertainty in the Mainstream 26 3 International Legal Personality 79 4 The Use of Force 110 5American Legal Cultures of Collective Security 140 6 Marxism and International Law 163 7Resistances to the Neoliberal International Economic Order 193 8From an Order of Fear to One of Respect 221 Index 249 M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page v Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Jobs PREFACE AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Normally a preface will give a list of the names of friends who have taken the trouble to read drafts of the manuscript, but I have found myself spontaneously adopting a slightly different and, I believe, more rigorous course. In the final stages of writing, over the last two years or so, I have accepted offers to participate in workshops where I could attempt a dry run of my ideas. As a consequence the work has had considerable feedback, but a price of participation is that versions of parts of the work have been published or are being published. This book is in a remote sense a sequel to The Decay of International Law published by Manchester University Press in 1986. It takes up some of the themes of the first book: the contested role of legal doctrine, the problematic character of custom as a source of law, and the relationship of the state to the nation in the theory of inter- national legal personality. However, on this occasion attention is devoted less to a critique of international lawyers and more to a rethinking of the tasks an international lawyer might undertake. There is here a real effort to break free of what I regard as irrelevant categories of thinking, although this always carries with it the risk that the discipline no longer recognizes what one is doing and reacts rather forcefully – this is what I mean by feedback. For instance, I presented the first fifteen pages of Chapter 1 of the present book at a conference of French and Spanish international lawyers at Palma, Majorca, in May 2005. 1 The somewhat outraged response to my views can be understood, at least in part, by the sense, especially marked among continental international lawyers, that they are legal technicians and should not be expected to assume a creative intellectual role, which implies political and moral responsibilities. 2 Indeed, the view of the international lawyer as a thinker or intellec- tual is regarded as subversive and even dangerous, no matter how innocuous his message, precisely because it does not find its way into a recognizable technical path. 3 And this is the reaction of quite close and sympathetic friends and colleagues, such as Pierre-Marie Dupuy M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page vi Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Job and Karel Wellens. The marriage of philosophy and international law, so evident to Vitoria, Suárez, Grotius, and Pufendorf, is now quite firmly not to be revived. It is even presumptuous to attempt it, a for- getting of the modest place that belongs to the international legal technician. The Decay of International Law met with very supportive reviews from David Kennedy and Peter Goodrich, which may have led to my being identified as a critical legal theorist, given the immense author- ity of these figures in the critical canon. This is very honorable company. However, there are a number of important respects in which I am, for better or worse, distinguishable from the Critical School. For instance, there is a history behind Chapter 6 of the book, which was first presented as part of a colloquium in the Hague Residence of Leiden University in September 2003. 4 At this seminar, organized by Susan Marks and Miklos Redner, there was a passion- ate debate between my friend and colleague Martti Koskenniemi and me, about my antiquated ‘’60s Leftism,’ which it is true postmodern critical legal scholars have mostly left behind. 5 Indeed the works of Foucault and Baudrillard are premised on the collapse of the Left after 1968. I very much sympathize with this fact. 6 However, I believe nothing has changed in the socio-economic conditions of the world, which justified the original reformist zeal of the Left, and this chapter is a passionate, if unfashionable manifesto against the abandonment of the wider socio-economic picture. It has a ‘’60s’ anti-American tone, which is ‘uncool,’ a point to which I will return later. A further ‘uncool’ aspect of my work, which is evident in Chapter 6, is my belief in the right to self-determination of small nations. Indeed, their right to form states is still the best chance they have to organize and protect themselves in the face of globalization – a thoroughly modernist idea. There is hardly a series of propositions that could be more unfashionable in postmodern critical legal circles. I have been struggling with the idea of the apparent priority of states over nations in international law discourse for many years and pieces of my argument in Chapters 3 and 7 have appeared before. 7 My approach is not at all influenced by the desire to accommodate liberal political theory, which I consider very briefly in Chapter 7. Instead, my aim here is merely to show the relative backwardness historically of the idea of the state in relation to the idea of the nation. The latter idea represents a democratic advance and epistemological progress. It is only the most deplorable stepmotherly meanness of the discipline of international law which leads it to set so many hurdles in the way Preface and Acknowledgments vii M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page vii Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Jo of the free expression of peoples. No new nation should have to explain itself to self-styled liberal opinion in the old Western European or North American nations, whether in its positivist or its postmodern mood. Another ‘uncool’ feature will appear to be the book’s ‘anti- American’ tone, especially in Chapter 5, ‘American Legal Cultures ’. I think this chapter is a rather standard exercise in postmodern cultural critique, an immanent critique of American discourse, based almost entirely on quite conservative American sources, particular Protestant American theological writing and classical American his- toriography. However, when I presented substantially the same paper at an international seminar in Innsbruck, organized by Hans Koechler, some European reactions evidenced unease at possible scapegoating of one country. 8 For myself there is the question of accepting responsibility as an international lawyer to confront actual problems. The US has been until the present the leading country to accept responsibility for the maintenance of international order. Critical reflection on American practice has to be central to what an international lawyer does. In the appendix to Chapter 4, I consider the postmodern lethargy of Europe when it comes to accepting such responsibility, and one sees it again at the time of writing in the initial reluctance of Europeans to contribute effectively to peacekeeping in Lebanon in August 2006. This reluctance is now changing and it may be that the anemic mood in Europe is becoming a thing of the past. Koechler’s forum in Innsbruck was in any case free of the Chekhovian quality of much continental European international law debate. Nonetheless, there is one fundamental sense in which I think this work remains profoundly critical, indeed postmodern and that is my final insistence upon a plurality of methods for undertaking inter- national law as an intellectual task in which the only sovereign the jurist should recognize is his or her own intellectual conscience. If statesmen want their treaties and judges want their decisions to be analyzed and expounded, they can hire their own officials to do it for them. Such exercises are useful, but they are no more than what I call legal dogmatics in Chapter 1 of the book. What still needs to be done is precisely to indulge one’s search for the foundations of one’s own legitimacy, which obviously cannot be found in the terms of Article 38(1)(d) of the Statute of the International Court of Justice. It merely allows that the views of distinguished jurists could be evidence of the existence of rules of international law. A renewed role for doctrine must at present lead the international lawyer in search of intellectual viii Philosophy of International Law M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page viii Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's J tasks, which his colleagues will not recognize as legal. In that case the struggle is to see who can finally appropriate the title ‘legal.’ In my view there is much more to do than to provide analytical indexes of treaties and judicial decisions. I believe that in Chapters 7 and 8 I merely recall the wider role that doctrine had until Vattel. As I was finishing this book, I was approached by a young international rela- tions scholar, Daniel Joyce, to make a contribution to a symposium on ‘Fear and International Order.’ 9 This appeared as a direct chal- lenge from a student of international relations to test the most radical chapter of the book at the hands of anonymous peer reviewers from that discipline. The feedback was very favorable. I believe this experi- ence is confirmation that the audience I am trying to address in the concluding two chapters has to be this wider one of quite simply humanist scholarship, not marked by any particular discipline. In his contribution to Law after Ground Zero, Bill Bowring quotes at length from the Decay of International Law. However, he goes on to prefer the expression used by David Chandler, a political scientist, as the title of his own chapter, ‘The Degradation of International Law?’ International law is no longer accepted by Western powers as a curb on the use of force. They prefer to appeal to what they call international justice, leading thereby to the degradation, not the development, of international law. 10 There is a crisis of acceptance of international law, which is not confined to a few restless, ‘postmod- ern’ legal spirits, but belongs to the widespread refusal of any place for international law in world society. International lawyers have to address this society, which they cannot simply do through authori- tarian appeals to their own legal dogmatics. They have to find a lan- guage, which others can speak. Indeed the point of the title of this book, Philosophy of International Law, is that they have to learn to use many languages. While I have been completing this book, I have also been working on another, an analysis of the form of legal advising, which takes place in departments of the British government when it is making foreign policy decisions. The logic of such work is quite different from this book. It endeavors to be purely positivist historical research, as far as that is possible in the practice of history. However, underlying such work is the wish to set standards for international legal posi- tivism which I think it does not set itself. International legal posi- tivism, insofar as it is not merely an aesthetic experience for those adhering to it, is an ideology for the celebration of the freedom of states. It is not, in my view, a framework for the analysis of a social Preface and Acknowledgments ix M637 CARTY PRE M/UP.qxd 16/1/07 9:45 AM Page ix Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Job [...]... Implications for International Law Teaching,’ 78 R Y Jennings, ‘The State of International Law Today,’ Journal of the Society of the Public Teachers of Law (1957–58) 95 at 96 Preface to the Annual Digest of International Law Cases, Years 1925 and 1926 (1929) x Ibid Crawford, ‘Public International Law in Twentieth-century England,’ 700 See further A Carty, ‘Visions of the Past of International Society, Law, History... the study of international law and the study of ethics Johnson blames this not on John Austin, who did not oppose international law as form of international morality, but on the international lawyers themselves, who wished to make their subject appeal to their fellow law school colleagues This led English international lawyers, wishing to impress their colleagues with the positive character of international. .. Divergences in International Law Traditions’, European Journal of International Law (2000) extracts from 716–32, with acknowledgment to Oxford University Press Chapter 7, pp 203–10, 213–18 appeared in ‘The National as a Meta-Concept of International Economic Law , in Asif Qureshi (ed.), Perspectives in International Economic Law (2002) extracts from 69–76, with acknowledgment to Kluwer Law International. .. first edition of his International Law (1900) Smith held numerous of ces of state, but, for Johnson, the most significant example of the practice was Sir William Harcourt, who was both M637 CARTY TEXT M/UP.qxd 24 28 29 30 31 32 33 34 35 36 37 38 39 40 41 16/1/07 9:46 AM Page 24 Gary Gary's G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Jo Philosophy of International Law Whewell Professor of International Law in Cambridge... the Practice of States: The British Archives in Relation to the 1957 Oman and Muscat Incident,’ The Singapore Yearbook of International Law, IX (2005), 75–85, with the permission of the Faculty of Law, Singapore National University; and appendix to Chapter 4, ‘The UK Invasion of Iraq as a Recent United Kingdom “Contribution to International Law ’, in the European Journal of International Law 16 (2005),... G4:Users:Gary:Public:Gary's Jobs Philosophy of International Law x reality So I have not been able to resist the ‘uncool’ idea of including as annexes to Chapters 2 and 4 studies which I believe expose the true nature of arguments about general customary law and about the legitimacy of the use of force in international relations.11 The influence of the legal concepts is not negligible However, they are part of the traditional... the conduct of their public affairs.48 THE STRUCTURE OF THIS BOOK What follows in the next three chapters, on the sources of international law, international legal personality, and the law relating to the use of force, may well appear to show some familiarity with the usual topics of a general course on international law However, their aim is to introduce the problems of fragmentation of statist language... language of sources as used by an as august a body as the International Court of Justice, fails to express the reality of the forms of legal consciousness in contemporary international society The chapter on sources does not offer a theory of justiciability, nor does it attempt a sociological critique of the professional limitations of the judges, although both are implicit in the critique of the Court’s... auto-interpretation of the extent of obligation Given the preponderance of the state, the role for doctrine has become marginalized and confined to the question whether international law is law at all Perhaps the majority view among the profession is that the question is unnecessary Emer de Vattel made the point that international law is a law precisely suited to the nature of the state, as a form of independent... survey of the English tradition of international law Johnson quotes F E Smith (later the Earl of Birkenhead) referring to it as an English tradition that ‘Professors of International Law shall also be men of affairs.’27 There is no mistaking McNair’s unease with this intellectual atmosphere He remarks how the nineteenth-century textbook was a descriptive rather than an analytical work, a history of international . Case Edinburgh University Press 22 George Square Edinburgh EH8 9LF www.eup.ed.ac.uk ISBN 978 0 7486 2255 9 Edinburgh barcode Philosophy of International Law Philosophy of International Law ANTHONY. evidence of the existence of rules of international law. A renewed role for doctrine must at present lead the international lawyer in search of intellectual viii Philosophy of International Law M637. to the foundations of the discipline of international law. This book offers an internal critique of the discipline of international law whilst showing the necessary place for philosophy within

Ngày đăng: 11/06/2014, 12:43

Từ khóa liên quan

Mục lục

  • COVER

  • COPYRIGHT

  • CONTENTS

  • PREFACE AND ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

  • 1 WHAT PLACE FOR DOCTRINE IN A TIME OF FRAGMENTATION?

  • 2 CONTINUING UNCERTAINTY IN THE MAINSTREAM

  • 3 INTERNATIONAL LEGAL PERSONALITY

  • 4 THE USE OF FORCE

  • 5 AMERICAN LEGAL CULTURES OF COLLECTIVE SECURITY

  • 6 MARXISM AND INTERNATIONAL LAW

  • 7 RESISTANCES TO THE NEOLIBERAL INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC ORDER

  • 8 FROM AN ORDER OF FEAR TO ONE OF RESPECT

  • INDEX

Tài liệu cùng người dùng

  • Đang cập nhật ...

Tài liệu liên quan